Democracy: The God That Failed by Hans-Hermann Hoppe

From: Technotranscendence (neptune@mars.superlink.net)
Date: Mon Nov 12 2001 - 04:02:23 MST


Democracy: The God That Failed
by Hans-Hermann Hoppe

from http://www.lewrockwell.com/hoppe/hoppe4.html

At the request of LRC, Professor Hoppe discusses his extremely important new
book, Democracy: The God That Failed (Transaction Publishers, Rutgers, NJ:
2001).

Theory and History

On the most abstract level, I want to show how theory is indispensible in
correctly interpreting history. History - the sequence of events unfolding
in time - is "blind." It reveals nothing about causes and effects. We may
agree, for instance, that feudal Europe was poor, that monarchical Europe
was wealthier, and that democratic Europe is wealthier still, or that
nineteenth-century America with its low taxes and few regulations was poor,
while contemporary America with its high taxes and many regulations is rich.
Yet was Europe poor because of feudalism, and did it grow richer because of
monarchy and democracy? Or did Europe grow richer in spite of monarchy and
democracy? Or are these phenomena unrelated?

Likewise, is contemporary America wealthier because of higher taxes and more
regulations or in spite of them? That is, would America be even more
prosperous if taxes and regulations had remained at their nineteenth-century
levels? Historians qua historians cannot answer such questions, and no
amount of statistical data manipulation can change this fact. Every sequence
of empirical events is compatible with any of a number of rival, mutually
incompatible interpretations.

To make a decision regarding such incompatible interpretations, we need a
theory. By theory I mean a proposition whose validity does not depend on
further experience but can be established a priori. This is not to say that
one can do without experience altogether in establishing a theoretical
proposition. However, it is to say that even if experience is necessary,
theoretical insights extend and transcend logically beyond a particular
historical experience. Theoretical propositions are about necessary facts
and relations and, by implication, about impossibilities. Experience may
thus illustrate a theory. But historical experience can neither establish a
theorem nor refute it.

The Austrian School

Economic and political theory, especially of the Austrian variety, is a
treasure trove of such propositions. For instance, a larger quantity of a
good is preferred to a smaller amount of the same good; production must
precede consumption; what is consumed now cannot be consumed again in the
future; prices fixed below market-clearing prices will lead to lasting
shortages; without private property in production factors there can be no
factor prices, and without factor prices cost-accounting is impossible; an
increase in the supply of paper money cannot increase total social wealth
but can only redistribute existing wealth; monopoly (the absence of free
entry) leads to higher prices and lower product quality than competition; no
thing or part of a thing can be owned exclusively by more than one party at
a time; democracy (majority rule) and private property are incompatible.

Theory is no substitute for history, of course, yet without a firm grasp of
theory serious errors in the interpretation of historical data are
unavoidable. For instance, the outstanding historian Carroll Quigley claims
that the invention of fractional reserve banking has been a major cause of
the unprecedented expansion of wealth associated with the Industrial
Revolution, and countless historians have associated the economic plight of
Soviet-style socialism with the absence of democracy.

>From a theoretical viewpoint, such interpretations must be rejected
categorically. An increase in the paper money supply cannot lead to greater
prosperity but only to wealth redistribution. The explosion of wealth during
the Industrial Revolution took place despite fractional reserve banking.
Similarly, the economic plight of socialism cannot be due to the absence of
democracy. Instead, it is caused by the absence of private property in
factors of production. "Received history" is full of such
misinterpretations. Theory allows us to rule out certain historical reports
as impossible and incompatible with the nature of things. By the same token,
it allows us to uphold certain other things as historical possibilities,
even if they have not yet been tried.

Revisionist History

More interestingly, armed with elementary economic and political theory, I
present in my book a revisionist reconstruction of modern Western history:
of the rise of absolute monarchical states out of state-less feudal orders,
and the transformation, beginning with the French Revolution and essentially
completed with the end of World War I, of the Western world from monarchical
to democratic States, and the rise of the US to the rank of "universal
empire." Neo-conservative writers such as Francis Fukuyama have interpreted
this development as civilizational progress, and they proclaim the "End of
History" to have arrived with the triumph of Western - US - democracy and
its globalization (making the world safe for democracy).

Myth One

My theoretical interpretation is entirely different. It involves the
shattering of three historical myths. The first and most fundamental is the
myth that the emergence of states out of a prior, non-statist order has
caused subsequent economic and civilizational progress. In fact, theory
dictates that any progress must have occurred in spite - not because - of
the institution of a state.

A state is defined conventionally as an agency that exercises a compulsory
territorial monopoly of ultimate decison-making (jurisdiction) and of
taxation. By definition then, every state, regardless of its particular
constitution, is economically and ethically deficient. Every monopolist is
"bad" from the viewpoint of consumers. Monopoly is hereby understood as the
absence of free entry into a particular line of production: only one agency,
A, may produce X.

Any monopoly is "bad" for consumers because, shielded from potential new
entrants into its line of production, the price for its product will be high
er and the quality lower than with free entry. And a monopolist with
ultimate decison-making powers is particularly bad. While other monopolists
produce inferior goods, a monopolist judge, besides producing inferior
goods, will produce bads, because he who is the ultimate judge in every case
of conflict also has the last word in each conflict involving himself.
Consequently, instead of preventing and resolving conflict, a monopolist of
ultimate decision-making will cause and provoke conflict in order to settle
it to his own advantage.

Not only would no one accept such a monopoly judge provision, but no one
would ever agree to a provision that allowed this judge to determine the
price to be paid for his "service" unilaterally. Predictably, such a
monopolist would use up ever more resources (tax revenue) to produce fewer
goods and perpetrate more bads. This is not a prescription for protection
but for oppression and exploitation. The result of a state, then, is not
peaceful cooperation and social order, but conflict, provocation,
aggression, oppression, and impoverishment, i.e., de-civilization. This,
above all, is what the history of states illustrates. It is first and
foremost the history of countless millions of innocent state victims.

Myth Two

The second myth concerns the historic transition from absolute monarchies to
democratic states. Not only do neoconservatives interpret this development
as progress; there is near-universal agreement that democracy represents an
advance over monarchy and is the cause of economic and moral progress. This
interpretation is curious in light of the fact that democracy has been the
fountainhead of every form of socialism: of (European) democratic socialism
and (American) liberalism and neo-conservatism as well as of international
(Soviet) socialism, (Italian) fascism, and national (Nazi) socialism. More
importantly, however, theory contradicts this interpretation; whereas both
monarchies and democracies are deficient as states, democracy is worse than
monarchy.

Theoretically speaking, the transition from monarchy to democracy involves
no more or less than a hereditary monopoly "owner" - the prince or king -
being replaced by temporary and interchangeable - monopoly "caretakers" -
presidents, prime ministers, and members of parliament. Both kings and
presidents will produce bads, yet a king, because he "owns" the monopoly and
may sell or bequeath it, will care about the repercussions of his actions on
capital values. As the owner of the capital stock on "his" territory, the
king will be comparatively future-oriented. In order to preserve or enhance
the value of his property, he will exploit only moderately and
calculatingly. In contrast, a temporary and interchangeable democratic
caretaker does not own the country, but as long as he is in office he is
permitted to use it to his advantage. He owns its current use but not its
capital stock. This does not eliminate exploitation. Instead, it makes
exploitation shortsighted (present-oriented) and uncalculated, i.e., carried
out without regard for the value of the capital stock.

Nor is it an advantage of democracy that free entry into every state
position exists (whereas under monarchy entry is restricted by the king's
discretion). To the contrary, only competition in the production of goods is
a good thing. Competition in the production of bads is not good; in fact, it
is sheer evil. Kings, coming into their position by virtue of birth, might
be harmless dilettantes or decent men (and if they are "madmen," they will
be quickly restrained or if need be, killed, by close relatives concerned
with the possessions of the dynasty). In sharp contrast, the selection of
government rulers by means of popular elections makes it essentially
impossible for a harmless or decent person to ever rise to the top.
Presidents and prime ministers come into their position as a result of their
efficiency as morally uninhibited demagogues. Hence, democracy virtually
assures that only dangerous men will rise to the top of government.

In particular, democracy is seen as promoting an increase in the social rate
of time preference (present-orientation) or the "infantilization" of
society. It results in continually increased taxes, paper money and paper
money inflation, an unending flood of legislation, and a steadily growing
"public" debt. By the same token, democracy leads to lower savings,
increased legal uncertainty, moral relativism, lawlessness, and crime.
Further, democracy is a tool for wealth and income confiscation and
redistribution. It involves the legislative "taking" of the property of
some - the haves of something - and the "giving" of it to others - the
have-nots of things. And since it is presumably something valuable that is
being redistributed - of which the haves have too much and the have-nots too
little - any such redistribution implies that the incentive to be of value
or produce something valuable is systematically reduced. In other words, the
proportion of not-so-good people and not-so-good personal traits, habits,
and forms of conduct and appearance will increase, and life in society will
become increasingly unpleasant.

Last but not least, democracy is described as resulting in a radical change
in the conduct of war. Because they can externalize the costs of their own
aggression onto others (via taxes), both kings and presidents will be more
than 'normally' aggressive and warlike. However, a king's motive for war is
typically an ownership-inheritance dispute. The objective of his war is
tangible and territorial: to gain control over some piece of real estate and
its inhabitants. And to reach this objective it is in his interest to
distinguish between combatants (his enemies and targets of attack) and
non-combatants and their property (to be left out of the war and undamaged).
Democracy has transformed the limited wars of kings into total wars. The
motive for war has become ideological - democracy, liberty, civilization,
humanity. The objectives are intangible and elusive: the ideological
"conversion" of the losers preceded by their "unconditional" surrender
(which, because one can never be certain about the sincerity of conversion,
may require such means as the mass murder of civilians). And the distinction
between combatants and non-combatants becomes fuzzy and ultimately
disappears under democracy, and mass war involvement - the draft and popular
war rallies - as well as "collateral damage" become part of war strategy.

Myth Three

Finally, the third myth shattered is the belief that there is no alternative
to Western welfare-democracies a la US. Again, theory demonstrates
otherwise. First, this belief is false because the modern welfare-state is
not a "stable" economic system. It is bound to collapse under its own
parasitic weight, much like Russian-style socialism imploded a decade ago.
More importantly, however, an economically stable alternative to democracy
exists. The term I propose for this alternative is "natural order."

In a natural order every scarce resource, including all land, is owned
privately, every enterprise is funded by voluntarily paying customers or
private donors, and entry into every line of production, including that of
property protection, conflict arbitration, and peacemaking, is free. A large
part of my book concerns the explanation of the workings - the logic - of a
natural order and the requirements for the transformation from democracy to
a natural order.

Whereas states disarm their citizens so as to be able to rob them more
surely (thereby rendering them more vulnerable also to criminal and
terrorist attack), a natural order is characterized by an armed citizenry.
This feature is furthered by insurance companies, which play a prominent
role as providers of security and protection in a natural order. Insurers
will encourage gun ownership by offering lower premiums to armed (and
weapons-trained) clients. By their nature insurers are defensive agencies.
Only "accidental" - not: self-inflicted, caused or provoked - damage is
"insurable." Aggressors and provocateurs will be denied insurance coverage
and are thus weak. And because insurers must indemnify their clients in case
of victimization, they must be concerned constantly about the prevention of
criminal aggression, the recovery of misappropriated property, and the
apprehension of those liable for the damage in question.

Furthermore, the relationship between insurer and client is contractual. The
rules of the game are mutually accepted and fixed. An insurer cannot
"legislate," or unilaterally change the terms of the contract. In
particular, if an insurer wants to attract a voluntarily paying clientele,
it must provide for the foreseeable contingency of conflict in its
contracts, not only between its own clients but especially with clients of
other insurers. The only provision satisfactorily covering the latter
contingency is for an insurer to bind itself contractually to independent
third-party arbitration. However, not just any arbitration will do. The
conflicting insurers must agree on the arbitrator or arbitration agency, and
in order to be agreeable to insurers, an arbitrator must produce a product
(of legal procedure and substantive judgment) that embodies the widest
possible moral consensus among insurers and clients alike. Thus, contrary to
statist conditions, a natural order is characterized by stable and
predictable law and increased legal harmony.

Moreover, insurance companies promote the development of another "security
feature." States have not just disarmed their citizens by taking away their
weapons, democratic states in particular have also done so in stripping
their citizens of the right to exclusion and by promoting instead - through
various non-discrimination, affirmative action, and multiculturalist
policies - forced integration. In a natural order, the right to exclusion
inherent in the very idea of private property is restored to private
property owners.

Accordingly, to lower the production cost of security and improve its
quality, a natural order is characterized by increased discrimination,
segregation, spatial separation, uniculturalism (cultural homogeneity),
exclusivity, and exclusion. In addition, whereas states have undermined
intermediating social institutions (family households, churches, covenants,
communities, and clubs) and the associated ranks and layers of authority so
as to increase their own power vis-a-vis equal and isolated individuals, a
natural order is distinctly un-egalitarian: "elitist," "hierarchical,"
"proprietarian," "patriarchical," and "authoritorian," and its stability
depends essentially on the existence of a self-conscious natural -
voluntarily acknowledged - aristocracy.

Strategy

Finally, I discuss strategic matters and questions. How can a natural order
arise out of democracy? I explain the role of ideas, intellectuals, elites,
and public opinion in the legitimation and de-legitimation of state power.
In particular, I discuss the role of secession - and the proliferation of
independent political entities - as an important step toward the goal of
natural order, and I explain how to properly privatize "socialized" and
"public" property.

The book grew out of speeches I presented at various Mises Institute and CLS
conferences during the 1990s. These conferences, organized by Lew Rockwell,
Burt Blumert, and, until his death in 1995, Murray Rothbard, had the purpose
of advancing libertarianism by locating and anchoring abstract libertarian
theory historically, sociologically, and culturally and thereby creating
what has become known in the meantime as paleo-libertarianism (in contrast
to left-countercultural-libertarianism and cold-and-hot-war "new" and
"neo"-conservatism). The Rothbard-Rockwell Report, the precusor to LRC, was
the first and most immediate expression and reflection of this intellectual
movement. Others included The Costs of War, Reassessing the Presidency, and

The Irrepressible Rothbard. Democracy the God That Failed is my attempt to
define and give expression to the paleo-libertarian movement.



This archive was generated by hypermail 2.1.5 : Sat Nov 02 2002 - 08:11:56 MST