[p2p-research] Organising and Disorganising

Michel Bauwens michelsub2004 at gmail.com
Wed Nov 12 13:32:15 CET 2008


---------- Forwarded message ----------
From: Michel Bauwens <michelsub2004 at gmail.com>
Date: Wed, Nov 12, 2008 at 7:29 PM
Subject: Re: [SPAM] Re: Organising and Disorganising
To: Alison at Triarchy Press <alison at triarchypress.com>





Some time ago<http://blog.p2pfoundation.net/book-of-the-week-michael-thompsons-theory-of-governance/2008/11/03>,
we introduced Michael Thompson's book as Book of the Week, but we did not
get the excerpts in time to do a follow-up the same week.

As a reminder, this book (*Organising and
Disorganising<http://www.p2pfoundation.net/Organising_and_Disorganising>:
A Dynamic and Non-Linear Theory of Institutional Emergence and its
Implications*) posits five different solidarities or types of
intersubjective relations, and it puzzled me how it could be squared with
the typology that is at the basis of my own theorizing on peer to peer, i.e.
Alan Page Fiske's relational grammar.

But after receiving chapter 2 for excerpting, I now understand how the
approaches complement each other. The four basic solidarities of Thompson
can be matched with the fourfold typology of Fiske, and the fifth, which
Michael Thompson calls autonomy (the way of the hermit), is an integration
of the other four, that avoids their coercion and totalitarian tendencies.

Indeed, the way of the market, the way of hierarchy, the way of
egalitarianism and the way of fatalism are each based on different
metaphysical assumptions, views of nature and man that cannot be proven but
are strongly adhered to, and each category's adherents tries to mold the
world to its own image.

They are therefore inherently coercive. Obviously, if our own peer to peer
approach where to be this first stage egalitarianism, it would be coercive
as well, and I believe that it isn't. Since none of the four can ever be
eliminated as a basic feeling of the universe, we cannot propose a system
that wipes the other out; however, it is legitimate I believe to think that
just as the 3 other solidarities were once dominant, the fourth, peer to
peer or communal shareholding, can also becoming a core organizing principle
of society. But it should be a non-coercive core, which honours the other 3
modes.

Here are the excerpts from Michael Thompson, i.e. an explanation of the four
solidarities followed by what cultural theory can bring to their
understanding.

*Michael Thompson (Chapter 2):*

"** For upholders of the individualist solidarity, nature is benign - able
to recover from any exploitation (hence the iconic myth of nature,
illustrated in Figure 2.1: a ball that, no matter how profoundly disturbed,
always returns to stability) - and man is inherently self-seeking and
atomistic (i.e. the way the methodological individualists assume man is).
Trial and error, in self-organising ego-focused networks (markets), is the
way to go, with Adam Smith's invisible hand ensuring that people only do
well when others also benefit. Individualists, in consequence, trust others
until they give them reason not to and then retaliate in kind (the winning
"tit for tat" strategy in the iterated Prisoner's Dilemma game [Rapoport
1985]). They see it as only fair that (as in the joint stock company) those
who put most in get most out. Managing institutions that work "with the
grain of the market" (getting rid of environmentally harmful subsidies, for
instance) are what are needed.*

* * Nature, for those who bind themselves into the egalitarian solidarity,
is almost the exact opposite (hence the ball on the upturned basin) - fragile,
intricately interconnected and ephemeral - and man is essentially caring and
sharing (until corrupted by coercive and inegalitarian institutions: markets
and hierarchies). We must all tread lightly on the Earth, and it is not
enough that people start off equal; they must end up equal as well -
equality of result. Trust and levelling go hand in hand, and institutions
that distribute unequally are distrusted. Voluntary simplicity is the only
solution to our environmental problems, with the "precautionary principle"
being strictly enforced on those who are tempted not to share the simple
life.*

* * The world, in the hierarchical solidarity, is controllable. Nature is
stable until pushed beyond discoverable limits (hence the two humps), and
man is malleable: deeply flawed but redeemable by firm, long-lasting and
trustworthy institutions (i.e. the way the methodological collectivists
assume man is, as in "Give me the boy and I will give you the man"). Fair
distribution is by rank and station or, in the modern context, by need (with
the level of need being determined by expert and dispassionate authority).
Environmental management requires certified experts (to determine the
precise locations of nature's limits) and statutory regulation (to ensure
that all economic activity is then kept within those limits).*

* * Fatalist actors (or perhaps we should say non-actors, since their voice
is seldom heard in policy debates; if it was they wouldn't be fatalistic!) find
neither rhyme nor reason in nature, and know that man is fickle and
untrustworthy. Fairness, in consequence, is not to be found in this life,
and there is no possibility of effecting change for the better. "Defect
first" - the winning strategy in the one-off Prisoner's Dilemma - makes
sense here, given the unreliability of communication and the permanent
absence of prior acts of good faith. With no way of ever getting in sync
with nature (push the ball this way or that and the feedback is everywhere
the same), or of building trust with others, the fatalist's world (unlike
those of the other three solidarities) is one in which learning is
impossible. "Why bother?", therefore, is the rational management response.*

*These solidarities, in varying strengths and patterns of pairwise alliance,
are clearly discernible almost anywhere you care to look: in debates over
water engineering in South Asia (Gyawali 2001); in the international fora
where delegates struggle to do something about climate change (Thompson,
Rayner and Ney 1998; Verweij 2001); in the different ways international
regimes cope with trans-boundary risks such as water pollution (Verweij
2000) and municipalities go about the business of transport planning
(Hendriks 1994); in the various ways households set about making ends meet
(Dake and Thompson 1999); in the different diagnoses of the pensions crisis
in countries with ageing populations (Ney 1997); and in the different
panaceas that are variously championed and rejected by theorists of public
administration (Hood 1998), to mention but a few.*

*In all these examples we find that each solidarity, in creating a context
that is shaped by its distinctive premises, generates a storyline that
inevitably contradicts those that are generated by the other solidarities.
Yet, since each distils certain elements of experience and wisdom that are
missed by the others, and since each provides a clear expression of the way
in which a significant portion of the populace feels we should live with one
another and with nature, it is important that they all be taken into some
sort of account in the policy process. That, in essence, is the case for
clumsiness: the case that I have tried to be persuasive about in the
previous chapter*."

*2. A Cultural Theory of these patterns*

*Michael Thompson (Chapter 2):*

"*A quick recapitulation of the argument so far - a recapitulation,
moreover, that brings in the fifth solidarity - is a sensible first step on
the way to this proper theory, and it can be set out in the form of five
crucial observations. All five are to do with what is involved in going from
the classic markets-and-hierarchies distinction to the cultural theory
scheme with its five "eddies": its five recurrent regularities within an
endless transactional flux.*

*"Economic incentives and (or, perhaps, versus) social sanctions" is one way
of explaining the markets-and-hierarchies framing. Hierarchies enforce the
law of contract, without which markets would not work, and they also do
other vital things (such as repelling enemies); markets then get on with the
wealth-creating process of innovating, bidding and bargaining. Each, we can
see, needs the other, though of course there is always considerable
disagreement about just where the line between these two transactional
realms should be drawn - most famously, perhaps, in the titanic struggle, in
the first half of the last century, between Keynes and Hayek. Keynes wanted
a major role for hierarchy; Hayek saw that as "The Road To Serfdom" (Hayek
1944) and wanted the line pushed back as far as it would go. Either way, as
Keynes pointed out, a line has to be drawn, thereby winning on points, as it
were ("Game, set and match", in the estimation of his most recent biographer
[Skidelski 2000 p285]).*

*The same sort of uneasy symbiosis is evident in what is called "the new
institutional economics" (which, since it goes back to Williamson's 1975
book, is really quite long in the tooth: a bit like Oxford's New College,
which was new in the fourteenth century). In this framing, spiralling
transaction costs (as changing technology, for instance, renders quality
control more difficult and expensive) lead to market failure and to the
hierarchy having to step in to set prices; and, conversely, markets taking
over when transaction costs fall (as, for instance, they recently have - to
almost zero - on the Internet). Each of these ways of organising, moreover,
is seen as promoting a distinctive rationality - procedural and substantive
as they are sometimes called: hierarchies being primarily concerned with
propriety ("Who has the right to do what and to whom?"); markets being much
more outcome-focused ("The bottom line"). In this way, each rationality
legitimises one of these ways of organising and, in so doing, renders it
viable in an environment that contains the other.*

*Cultural theory does not reject this classic distinction, but it does add
the following crucial observations:*

*1. You cannot have hierarchies without hierarchists, nor markets without
individualists.*

*That is, the organisational requirements of the whole - the pattern of
relationships - must somehow be internalised by the parts. The
pattern-making, in other words, goes both ways - from the whole to the parts
and from the parts to the whole - and this goes on in such a way as to
strengthen that pattern and differentiate it from the other patterns. In
this way (and like the chicken and the egg) each becomes the cause of the
other: we create the patterns and the patterns create us. Individuality, in
consequence, is not within each of us but between us: the individual, in Jon
Elster's memorable phrase, is inherently relational.*

*2. If two rationalities are justifiable, as they obviously are here, then
the upholders of those rationalities will have to have different convictions
as to how the world is and people are: different social constructions of
nature, physical and human. Otherwise they could not justify their different
actions as being self-evidently sensible and moral, the world and people
being the way each of them insists they are. And, for contradictory
certainties such as these to persist, there must always be sufficient
uncertainty as to how the world, and the people in it, really are.*

*3. Since markets institute equality (of opportunity) and promote
competition whilst hierarchies institute inequality (status differences) and
restrain competition, there are two discriminators at work here.*

*A full typology, therefore, should contain the other two permutations:
equality without competition (egalitarianism) and inequality with
competition (fatalism).*

*4. Since it is possible to contemplate both hierarchies and markets without
having to be convinced that either's version - of how the world is and
people are - is true, and since the same holds for egalitarianism and
fatalism, there may well be a fifth way of organising (it is called
autonomy) that is stabilized by the deliberate avoidance of the sorts of
coercive involvement that are entailed in the other four. However, hermits
(as the upholders of autonomy have been dubbed) do not transcend the social
sphere, because they stabilize their distinctive way of organising in
contradistinction to the others. If the four "socially engaged" forms of
solidarity were not there the autonomous life would not be liveable. The
objection - "four permutations and five solidarities" - recedes once we
realise that the cross-over point of our two discriminators corresponds to a
rather strange "all-zero" permutation (this will become clearer in the next
chapter when these discriminators are recast, more correctly, as a
transaction matrix).*

*5. Though each pattern is made up of individuals and their transactions, we
should not assume that an individual is part of only one pattern.*

*Indeed, as Lockhart (1997) has pointed out, people who strive to keep all
their transactions on just one pattern are hard to live with - we call them
fanatics!*

*In general, if transactional spheres - workplace and home, for instance -
are fairly separate then an individual may lead different parts of his or
her life in different patterns. Just because we are physiologically
indivisible it does not follow that we are socially indivisible; hence the
need to think in terms of the dividual, and to take the form of social
solidarity (the pattern together with its viability conditions) as the unit
of analysis, not the individual.*

*These, then, are the barest bones of cultural theory. In the chapters that
follow I will try to put some dynamic flesh on these bones (particularly on
the fifth bone - the form of solidarity as the unit of analysis) and I will
try to do this in a way that will make sense to students of institutions: no
easy task, given my anti-dualistic and unobvious starting point. But
cultural theory does have one thing in its favour: its even-handedness.
Where students of institutions have long been faced with a stark choice -
methodological individualism or methodological collectivism - cultural
theory offers a welcome, and perhaps surprising, escape route: "a plague on
both your methodologies!*"
-------------- next part --------------
An HTML attachment was scrubbed...
URL: http://listcultures.org/pipermail/p2presearch_listcultures.org/attachments/20081112/27739cff/attachment-0001.html 


More information about the p2presearch mailing list